(Single slit / Diffraction grating / Uncertainty relation)
In this section, Feynman discusses the uncertainty of complementary variables
involving a slit and diffraction grating, as well as the uncertainty relation in wave theory. A more fitting title for this
section might be “Inherent
Uncertainty of Position and Momentum.” It emphasizes that while
measurement can increase uncertainty, the uncertainty itself is intrinsic to
the system rather than solely a result of measurement (as implied by the title,
“Measurement of Position
and Momentum”).
1. Single slit:
“How does the pattern become spread? To say it is
spread means that there is some chance for the particle to be moving up or
down, that is, to have a component of momentum up or down. We say chance and particle because
we can detect this diffraction pattern with a particle counter, and when the
counter receives the particle, say at C in Fig. 38–2, it
receives the entire particle, so that, in a classical sense,
the particle has a vertical momentum, in order to get from the slit up
to C (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 38–2).”
Feynman explains diffraction through a single slit
using a particle-based perspective. While this explanation aligns with quantum
mechanics’ probabilistic nature, it reflects Feynman’s preference for a particle-centric
view. In wave theory, light can be represented as wave
packets, which are superpositions of
waves with slightly different wavelengths. The wave packets may provide a better
understanding of diffraction, where the single slit acts as a device that
spreads the wave’s wavelength components across a range of angles. The
relationship between the slit width and the diffraction pattern can be understood
via the uncertainty principle:
narrowing the slit increases uncertainty in the momentum of wave packets,
resulting in a broader angular spread, and vice versa.
The spreading of wave packets by the slit can be interpreted
as an environmental interaction, but it is equivalent to a measurement. As
light passes through a slit, it becomes localized, effectively corresponding to
a position measurement. However, this localization in position introduces an
uncertainty in the vertical wave number ky, which is directly
related to the vertical momentum py (= ℏky). Based
on the wave theory, when the wave packet is highly localized, the momentum
uncertainty (Δpy) is large, causing greater spreading. In this
framework, the spreading of the wave packet is not a result of the particle
"moving up or down" in the classical sense, but rather an inherent
property of wave-like behavior arising from the superposition of wave
components.
“Sometimes people say
quantum mechanics is all wrong. When the particle arrived from the left, its
vertical momentum was zero. And now that it has gone through the slit, its
position is known. Both position and momentum seem to be known with arbitrary
accuracy (Feynman et
al., 1963, p. 38–3).”
It is worth mentioning that Einstein did not say quantum mechanics was
all wrong, but critiqued its
completeness. His concern was
whether quantum mechanics provides a complete description of reality or merely
reflects statistical ignorance of some deeper, hidden reality. Instead of
assuming a perfect correlation between a wave packet’s position and momentum,
it is crucial to recognize the predictive limitations of quantum mechanics. Once a particle or wave packet interacts with
the slit, its momentum is irreversibly disturbed, i.e., the act of measurement
(position localization) fundamentally alters the system, increasing momentum uncertainty.
However, questions about the nature of quantum correlations and their possible
connections to deeper underlying mechanisms continue to drive theoretical and
experimental investigations.
2. Diffraction
grating:
“Suppose
we have a grating with a large number of lines (Fig. 38–3), and
send a beam of particles at the grating…… That is, the waves which form the
diffraction pattern are waves which come from different parts of the grating.
The first ones that arrive come from the bottom end of the grating, from the
beginning of the wave train, and the rest of them come from later parts of the
wave train, coming from different parts of the grating, until the last one
finally arrives, and that involves a point in the wave train a
distance L behind the first point (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 38–3).”
It is remarkable that Feynman used Rayleigh’s
criterion of resolution to derive an uncertainty relation, but this criterion
is not based on a fundamental physical principle—it is a guideline or
convention for resolving two overlapping waves. The key factor in determining
the diffraction pattern produced by a grating is the spread of wavelengths
within the wave trains. The length of a wave train is crucial because it is
directly related to its wavelength spread (Δλ). A longer wave train has a narrower
spread of wavelengths, leading to sharper and distinct diffraction peaks, and
vice versa. The term wave train is appropriate here because it conveys
the idea of a longer wave, as compared to the shorter localized wave packet,
which is more apt for modeling particles passing through a single slit.
The sharpness of diffraction peaks is not
fundamentally limited by the grating itself but rather by the spectral
composition (distribution of wavelengths and relative strengths) of the wave
train. If the wavelength spread (Δλ) of
the wave train exceeds the grating’s resolving capability, the diffraction
pattern will remain blurred, regardless of the number of lines on the grating
or width of the slits. Interestingly, the distance L, corresponding to the wave
train’s coherence length, can also be interpreted as the minimum length
required for using the entire grating effectively. More important, the grating functions like a
Fourier transform, decomposing the wave train into its constituent wavelengths.
This is analogous to how the human ear—specifically, the cochlea, a
fluid-filled spiral structure—distinguishes sounds of different frequencies
(See below).
![]() |
(Source: Parker, 2018) |
3.
Uncertainty relation:
“Now this property of waves,
that the length of the wave train times the uncertainty of the wave number
associated with it is at least 2π, is a property that is known to everyone
who studies them. It has nothing to do with quantum mechanics. It is simply
that if we have a finite train, we cannot count the waves in it very precisely (Feynman et
al., 1963, p. 38–4).”
Feynman’s remark
underscores a fundamental fact: a finite wave train does not have a precisely defined wavelength (or wave
number). More generally, the product of uncertainties in wave number (Δk)
and position (Δx, the length of a wave packet or wave train) can be
normalized to a constant such as 2π or 1 for simplicity (see below), depending on the chosen units. This
reflects the nature of waves rather than being tied to any specific measurement
process. The spectral composition
of a wave train depends on its length: a long wave train consists of a
narrow spread of wavelengths, akin to playing a single note on a flute for an
extended time—an almost pure tone. Conversely, a short wave train has a broad range of frequencies, similar to pressing
all the keys on a piano simultaneously, thereby produces a short burst of sound.
In short, the length of the wave train tells us about how “pure” or “mixed” the
wave is (in terms of its wavelength).
![]() |
Source: Wave Equation, Wave Packet Solution |
The uncertainty relation in wave theory is closely related to Fourier series, where any wave can be represented as a sum of sinusoidal components. Though Feynman does not explicitly specify Fourier transforms, his discussion aligns with Fourier’s principles. Essentially, a shorter wave train needs more wave components of differing wavelengths to form its sharp edges and transient nature, whereas a longer wave train is dominated by a narrower set of frequencies, resulting in a smoother, more uniform waveform. This relation underscores the fundamental trade-off between localization in space and precision in wavelength, mirroring the uncertainty principle in quantum mechanics. This insight, deeply rooted in Fourier analysis, provides a mathematical foundation for understanding the intrinsic limits of measurement in both classical wave theory and quantum mechanics.
Note: The section title
“Measurement of position and momentum” could be misleading, as the uncertainty
relation applies universally to wave phenomena, not just quantum measurement. In a paper on the quantum postulate,
Bohr (1928) expressed
this clearly: “[r]igorously speaking, a
limited wave-field can only be obtained by the superposition of a manifold of
elementary waves corresponding to all values of ν and σx, σy, σz. But the order of magnitude of the mean difference
between these values for two elementary waves in the group is given in the most
favourable case by the condition Δt Δν = Δx Δσx = Δy Δσy = Δz Δσz =
1, where Δt, Δx,
Δy, Δz denote the extension of the wave-field in time and in the
directions of space corresponding to the co-ordinate axes. These relations —
well known from the theory of optical instruments, especially from Rayleigh's
investigation of the resolving power of spectral apparatus — express the
condition that the wave-trains extinguish each other by interference at the
space-time boundary of the wave-field.”
Review
Questions:
1.
How would you explain the spreading of a particle (or wave packet) through a
slit?
2.
Is it legitimate to derive an
uncertainty relation using the Rayleigh’s criterion of resolution?
3.
How would you explain inherent uncertainties using the Fourier Transform?
The
moral of the lesson: The uncertainty of
complementary variables in quantum mechanics—whether in a slit or diffraction
grating—can be changed by environmental conditions or measurement, however,
the uncertainty relation is already known
as an inherent property of waves before the quantum revolution.
References:
1. Bohr, N. (1928). The Quantum Postulate and the Recent
Development of Atomic Theory. Nature, 121, 580-590.
2. Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R. B., & Sands,
M. (1963). The Feynman Lectures on
Physics, Vol I: Mainly mechanics, radiation, and
heat. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
3. Parker, J. A. (2018). Image
reconstruction in radiology. Boca Raton, FL: CRC press.