(Relativism / Empiricism / Mach’s Positivism)
In this section, Feynman
discusses relativism, empiricism, and Mach’s positivism.
1. Relativism:
“That all is relative is a consequence of Einstein, and it has profound influences
on our ideas (Feynman et al., 1963, section 16–1 Relativity and the philosophers).”
According to
Feynman, cocktail-party philosophers simply interpret Einstein’s theory as “all
is relative.” These philosophers would explain that phenomena depend on one’s
frame of reference has been demonstrated in physics. That is, the idea of
“things depend upon your frame of reference” has a profound effect on modern
thought. The philosophical view that “all is relative” is sometimes described
as relativism. In a sense, this misconception of the special theory of
relativity can be attributed to the term relativity.
On the contrary, there are absolute truths and invariant quantities in special
relativity.
One may expect Feynman to elaborate on the importance
of invariants that is in contrast to relativism. For example, in Jammer’s (1999)
words, “mathematician Felix Klein and physicist Arnold Sommerfeld suggested that the name
‘theory of relativity’ should be replaced by ‘theory of invariants’ because the
theory is merely a theory of the invariants of the Lorentz transformation (p.
33).” On the other hand, Minkowski
(1907) has developed the concept of invariant (absolute) space-time interval
and suggested the name “the postulate of the absolute world (p. 117).” Importantly,
the light postulate states that the speed of light is invariant (or absolute) in
all inertial frames of reference. Furthermore, the equations (e.g., four-momentum)
in the special theory of relativity are invariant.
2. Empiricism:
“Our inability
to detect absolute motion is a result of experiment and not a result of
plain thought, as we can easily illustrate (Feynman et al.,
1963, section 16–1 Relativity and the
philosophers).”
Feynman
explains that a consequence of relativity was the development of empiricism
which said, “You can only define what you can measure.... The physicists should
have realized that they can talk only about what they can measure.” In other
words, the whole problem of whether
one can define absolute
velocity is the same as the problem of whether one can measure absolute
velocity in an experiment without looking outside. However, another consequence is the development of
operationalism: the idea of an
operational definition in which “the concept is synonymous with the corresponding
set of operations (Bridgman, 1927, p. 5).” Bridgman further suggests that a
dozen operating procedures in measuring a physical quantity may lead to a dozen
of different concepts.
Empiricism is a philosophy of science that emphasizes the importance of experimental evidence. In a lecture delivered in
Cornell University, Feynman (1965) says that “[i]t does not make any difference
how beautiful your guess is. It does not make any difference how smart you are,
who made the guess, or what his name is - if it disagrees with experiment it is
wrong (p. 156).” Thus, some may argue that Feynman is an empiricist because he advocates
the role of empirical evidence in the development of physical laws. However, in
“Surely, You’re Joking, Mr. Feynman!,” Feynman questioned empirical results of
Telegdi’s experiment on parity violation. Interestingly, Telegdi (1989) praises
Feynman and writes that “[h]e understood experiments deeply and could suggest sources of error that had escaped
the experimenters themselves (p. 85).”
3. Mach’s
Positivism:
“Now that the
motion is no longer absolute, but is a motion relative to the nebulae,
it becomes a mysterious question, and a question that can be answered only by
experiment (Feynman et al., 1963, section 16–1 Relativity and the philosophers).”
Feynman states Mach’s philosophy as one cannot detect any motion
except by looking outside. (Mach distrusts concepts that cannot be verified by
observable evidence.) Moreover, Feynman argues that Mach’s philosophy is not
true because the Earth’s rotation on its axis can be determined using Foucault
pendulum without looking at the stars. However, Bondi and Samuel (1997) applies Mach’s
principle to explain a small precession (or Lense-Thirring precession) of the Foucault plane. More
important, Einstein recognized Mach’s influence in questioning the notion of
absolute space and time that helped to develop the special theory of relativity.
Mach’s philosophy of science is more appropriately
known as Mach’s positivism instead of simply positivism or phenomenalism.
Mach’s positivism can be
described by Einstein’s words: “Science is nothing else but
the comparing and ordering of our observations according to the methods and
angles which we learn particularly by trial and error... As results of this ordering
abstract concepts and the rules of their connection appear... Concepts have
meaning only if we can point to objects to which they refer and to the rules by
which they are assigned to these objects (Frank, 1952, p.
271).” Despite his criticisms of Mach’s positivism, Feynman explores
how to incorporate Mach’s principle in quantum mechanics and gravitation theory (Feynman, Morinigo, & Wagner, 1995). Furthermore, Feynman discussed Mach’s principle with Wheeler before
performing a sprinkler’s experiment that resulted in Feynman banished from the laboratory (Wheeler, 1989).
Note: The philosophical underpinning of Poincaré’s principle of relativity is essentially
geometric conventionalism. For example, Poincaré (1902) writes that ‘[e]xperiment guides us in this choice, which it
does not impose on us. It tells us not what is the truest, but what is the most
convenient geometry (pp. 71-72).” Poincare’s
conventionalism can be described as a “philosophy asserted that fundamental
scientific principles are not reflections of the ‘real’ nature of the universe
but are convenient ways of describing the natural world insofar as they are not
contradicted by observation or experiment (Nye, 1979, p. 107). Thus, Feynman could have clarified whether the method
of synchronizing clocks in special relativity is also a matter of convention.
Questions for discussion:
1. Why is relativism (“all is relative”) a
misconception of Einstein’s special theory of relativity?
2. How would you justify empiricism which is related to “you can only define what you can
measure?”
3. How do you explain that “one cannot detect any motion except by looking outside” (using a
smartphone that has a built-in GPS)?
The moral of the
lesson: currently, we have a much more humble point of view of our
physical laws—everything can be wrong! (Mach’s philosophy may seem silly
to physicists, but it helps to question the notion of absolute space and time.)
References:
1. Bondi, H., & Samuel, J.
(1997). The Lense-Thirring effect and Mach’s principle. Physics Letters A,
228(3), 121-126.
2. Bridgman, P. W. (1927). The
Logic of Modern Physics. New York: Macmillan.
3. Feynman, R. P. (1965). The
character of physical law. Cambridge: MIT Press.
4. Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R. B., & Sands, M. (1963). The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Vol I: Mainly mechanics, radiation, and
heat. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
5. Feynman, R. P., Morinigo, F. B., & Wagner, W. G. (1995). Feynman Lectures
on gravitation (B. Hatfield, ed.).
Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
6. Frank, P. (1951). Einstein, Mach, and logical
positivism. In Paul Schilpp (Ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist. La
Salle, Illinois: Open
Court Press. pp. 270-286.
7. Jammer, M. (1999). Einstein and Religion: Physics and
Theology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
8. Minkowski,
H. (1907). Space
and Time. In Petkov, V., (Ed.), Minkowski’s Papers on Relativity. Moscu:
Minkowski Institute Press.
9. Nye, M. J. (1979). The Boutroux circle and
Poincaré's conventionalism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 40(1), 107-120.
10. Poincaré, H. (1902/1952). Science
and hypothesis. Mineola, NY: Dover.
11. Telegdi, V. (1989). A Lowbrow's View of Feynman. Physics Today, 42(2), 85.
12. Wheeler, J. A.
(1989). The Young Feynman. Physics Today,
42(2), 24-28.
No comments:
Post a Comment