Conscious observer / Unmeasurable concept / Classical indeterminism
In
this section, Feynman addresses several philosophical issues in quantum
mechanics, including the role of the conscious observer, unmeasurable concepts,
and classical indeterminism. This indicates that he did not adhere to the “shut
up and calculate” mindset—a phrase popularized by David Mermin and sometimes mistakenly
attributed to Feynman. While the slogan reflects a pragmatic attitude of many
physicists toward philosophical debates, it overlooks Feynman’s willingness to
engage with foundational questions, even as he dismissed metaphysical
speculation.
Feynman’s colleague Murray Gell-Mann was
more openly contemptuous of philosophy. As described in George Johnson’s (1999)
biography Strange Beauty, Gell-Mann considered philosophy as a waste of
time—for instance, debating over the “reality” of quarks. In one (possibly
apocryphal) anecdote, he is said to readily provide a “doctor’s note” when
asked about philosophical issues, saying, “I’m sorry, I cannot talk about
philosophy. My doctor said it’s bad for my blood pressure.” Ironically,
Gell-Mann playfully named his quark classification scheme the “Eightfold Way,”
referencing Buddhist philosophy.
Feynman’s attitude toward philosophy was
possibly ambivalent. He famously said, “Philosophy of science is about as
useful to scientists as ornithology is to birds”—implying that scientists don’t
need it to do good science. Yet he included a “Philosophy” section in his paper
on gauge theories, though he likely meant physical significance rather than
philosophical inquiry. In a 1962 letter to his wife Gweneth from a Warsaw
conference, Feynman wrote, “…it is not good for my blood pressure...,” expressing
frustration with unproductive research on gravitational theory—not philosophy
per se.
1. Conscious observer
“The observer was sometimes important in prequantum physics, but only in
a rather trivial sense. The problem has been raised: if a tree falls in a
forest and there is nobody there to hear it, does it make a noise? A real tree
falling in a real forest makes a sound, of course, even if
nobody is there (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 38-8).”
Feynman’s
view assumes a mind-independent reality: physical processes—such as the
generation of sound waves—occur regardless of conscious observers. In his lectures on
gravitation for postgraduates, Feynman (1995) comments, “…are you the observer? Then there is no reality to the
world after you are dead? I know a number of otherwise respectable physicists
who have bought life insurance. By what philosophy will the universe without
man be understood? (p. 14).” This passage lightly mocks the
idea that consciousness is necessary for reality to exist. While thinkers such
as von Neumann, Wigner, and Penrose have proposed consciousness-based
interpretations of quantum mechanics, their ideas remain outside mainstream
physics. Feynman’s mentor, John Wheeler, pushed the discussion further by
suggesting an active role for observers—though not necessarily linking it
directly to human consciousness.
In the same Lectures on
Gravitation, Feynman (1995) examines
the distinction between external and internal observers in quantum mechanics:
“… what may properly be described by an amplitude to an
external observer, is not necessarily well described by a similar amplitude
when the observer is part of the amplitude. Thus the external observer of the
usual quantum mechanics is in a peculiar position. In order to find out whether
the cat is alive or dead, he makes a little hole in the box and looks; it is
only after he has made his measurement that the system is in a well-defined
final state; but clearly, from the point of view of the internal observer, the
results of this measurement by the external observer are determined by a
probability, not an amplitude (p. 13).”
This
passage explores central ideas from the Wigner’s friend thought experiment,
which raises questions about observer-dependent reality. In such scenarios:
1.
The external observer (Wigner) describes the entire
system—including the friend and the cat—using a wavefunction that remains in
superposition until measurement is made.
2.
The internal observer (the friend) experiences a
definite outcome—either the cat is alive or dead—not a superposition.
While
these two descriptions may appear contradictory, they illustrate the challenge
of reconciling quantum mechanics across different observational perspectives. Rather
than exposing a logical inconsistency in the theory, the contrast points to controversies
in defining objective reality in quantum mechanics. Potential resolutions
depend on one’s philosophical position—whether one emphasizes consciousness, decoherence,
or treats the wavefunction as a mathematical tool.
To avoid the philosophical
problems surrounding consciousness, some physicists prefer the term “agent” or “participant”
instead of “observer.” In modern interpretations such as Quantum Bayesianism
(QBism), an agent is an active
participant who assigns probabilities based on their personal expectations and
experiences. In this framework, quantum events (e.g., an atom’s decay) do not possess
definite outcomes until the agent interacts with the system. That is,
unmeasured properties are not merely unknown; they are fundamentally undefined.
QBism redefines the observer not as a metaphysical entity or conscious mind, but
as a decision-maker who updates their knowledge through measurement. The
focus shifts from an objective wavefunction collapse to subjective process
of Bayesian probability updating. Notably, the framework allows even an AI
robot: it can perform experiments and revise assigned probabilities, without
raising questions about consciousness.
2. Unmeasurable concept
“The situation in the sciences is this: A concept or an idea which cannot
be measured or cannot be referred directly to experiment may or may not be
useful. It need not exist in a theory. In other words, suppose we compare the
classical theory of the world with the quantum theory of the world, and suppose
that it is true experimentally that we can measure position and momentum only
imprecisely (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 38-10).”
In
Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics, Bohr
(1949) writes “Isolated material particles are abstractions, their properties
being definable and observable only through their interaction with other
systems.” His statement aligns closely with empiricism and shares some tenets of
logical positivism, but it does not strictly adhere to either philosophy. Specifically,
logical positivists would argue that a statement is cognitively meaningful only
if it is either analytically true (true by definition or logic, like
mathematics) or empirically verifiable (testable through observation or
experiment). For instance, Bohr rejected the notion of an “electron path” in
quantum mechanics because it lacked direct experimental verification. On the contrary,
in his development of quantum electrodynamics (QED), Feynman revived the concept
of "paths," relating them to abstract mathematical amplitudes to be
summed over all possible paths a particle might take.
During an interview, Feynman recounts his encounter with Bohr’s objections of his idea: “Bohr got up and said: ‘Already in 1925, 1926, we knew that the classical idea of a trajectory or a path is not legitimate in quantum mechanics; one could not talk about the trajectory of an electron in the atom, because it was something not observable.’ In other words, he was telling me about the uncertainty principle. It became clear to me that there was no communication between what I was trying to say and they were thinking. Bohr thought that I didn’t know the uncertainty principle … Bohr was concerned about the uncertainty principle and the proper use of quantum mechanics. To tell a guy that he doesn’t know quantum mechanics—well, it didn’t make me angry, it just made me realize that he [Bohr] didn’t know what I was talking about, and it was hopeless to try to explain it further. I gave up, I simply gave up… (Mehra, 1994, p. 248).” Feynman’s approach to quantum mechanics was pragmatic, treating even unmeasurable concepts as useful computational tools for generating accurate predictions.
Feynman’s
path integral approach to quantum mechanics is based on the principle of
summing over all possible histories, treating a particle as if it explores
every conceivable path between two points. These include not only classical trajectories
but also mathematically useful—though physically implausible—constructs, such
as those that move backward in time (often associated with antiparticles) or
imaginary-time paths used in certain calculations. Although the sum over all
paths yields experimentally verifiable probabilities, the individual paths
themselves are not observable. A related example arises in Feynman diagrams,
where internal lines represent virtual particles. These entities cannot be
directly detected, yet they play a crucial role in calculating observable
quantities and explaining interaction processes. Such examples highlight a key
feature of theoretical physics: concepts that cannot be directly measured or
empirically verified may still have significant explanatory and predictive
value.
3. Classical indeterminism
“It is therefore not fair to say that from the apparent freedom and
indeterminacy of the human mind, we should have realized that classical ‘deterministic’
physics could not ever hope to understand it, and to welcome quantum mechanics
as a release from a ‘completely mechanistic’ universe. For already in classical
mechanics there was indeterminability from a practical point of view (Feynman
et al., 1963, p. 38-10).”
Feynman
points out a subtle but profound insight about classical physics: although it
is deterministic in principle, it can be indeterminate in practice.
According to classical mechanics, perfect knowledge of a system's initial
conditions would theoretically enable exact prediction of its future behavior.
However, in real-world scenarios, even infinitesimal measurement uncertainties can
result in exponentially diverging outcomes over time—a phenomenon known as the butterfly
effect. This sensitivity to initial conditions means that while the present
strictly determines the future in theory, an approximate present
fails to reliably predict an approximate future. As Lorenz
(1963) succinctly put it: “When the present determines the future, but
the approximate present does not approximately determine the future.” This
fundamental limitation, central to chaos theory, reveals how deterministic
systems can nevertheless produce effectively unpredictable behavior.
Classical
indeterminism refers to the practical unpredictability of systems governed by
deterministic laws. While classical mechanics is deterministic in principle,
several factors undermine our ability to predict outcomes with certainty in
practice. At least four key reasons contribute to this indeterminism:
1.
Sensitivity to Initial Conditions: Even infinitesimal uncertainties lead to exponentially
diverging outcomes over time.
2.
Measurement Precision limits: Absolute precision is physically unattainable and
these microscopic uncertainties grow through interactions.
3.
Computational Intractability: While the behavior of individual particles in
macroscopic systems is theoretically governed by classical mechanics, solving
equations for systems involving something on the order of Avogadro’s number of
particles becomes computationally unfeasible.
4.
Analytical Unsolvability: Even simple systems (like the three-body problem)
defy closed-form solutions, requiring numerical approximations that accumulate
errors.
This
shows that unpredictability isn’t unique to quantum mechanics—it emerges even
in purely classical physics contexts.
Perhaps
Feynman could have acknowledged the pioneering insights of Poincaré into
classical indeterminism. Decades before chaos theory's formalization,
Poincaré's study of the three-body problem revealed a profound truth in
celestial mechanics: deterministic systems can exhibit inherent
unpredictability. As Poincaré (1908) presciently noted in Science and Method:
“…it may happen that small differences in the initial conditions produce very
great differences in the final phenomena. A small error in the former will
produce an enormous error in the latter. Prediction becomes impossible, and we
have the fortuitous phenomenon (p. 68).” In articulating this sensitivity to
initial conditions, Poincaré anticipated what would much later be recognized as
a hallmark of chaotic systems. Poincaré’s work, long underappreciated, thus
serves as a conceptual bridge between classical determinism and the modern
understanding of dynamical chaos.
Review
Questions:
1.
Does quantum mechanics require the concept of an observer?
2.
Should physicists use concepts that cannot be directly connected to experiment?
3.
How would you explain classical indeterminism?
The
Moral of the Lesson: Although Feynman is often associated with the
pragmatic “shut up and calculate” mindset, this section reveals that he
engaged with philosophical issues of quantum mechanics. He was not dismissive
of philosophy itself, but of poor or misguided philosophy. Feynman sought to
clarify the implications of quantum theory while rejecting pseudoscientific
speculation and conceptual overreach —a lesson in how to think critically
about profound ideas.
References:
Bohr,
N. (1949). Discussion with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic
physics. In Niels Bohr Collected Works (Vol. 7, pp. 339-381). Amsterdam,
Netherlands: Elsevier.
Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R. B., & Sands, M. (1963). The
Feynman Lectures on Physics, Vol I: Mainly mechanics, radiation, and heat. Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley.
Feynman, R. P., Morinigo, F. B., & Wagner, W. G.
(1995). Feynman
Lectures on gravitation (B.
Hatfield, ed.). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Johnson, G. (2000). Strange beauty: Murray
Gell-Mann and the revolution in twentieth-century physics. New York, NY: Vintage.
Lorenz,
E. N. (1963). Deterministic nonperiodic flow. Journal of the Atmospheric
Sciences, 20(2), 130–141.
Mehra, J. (1994). The Beat of a Different Drum: The life and science of Richard Feynman. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Poincaré, H. (1908). Science and Method
(original French: La science et la méthode). London,
UK: Thomas Nelson & Sons.
No comments:
Post a Comment