Idealizations / Approximations / Limitations
Though
titled Properties of Matter, this section might be more fittingly named Introduction
to Thermodynamics, as Feynman briefly discusses the theory’s foundational
idealizations, mathematical approximations, and intrinsic limitations. To appreciate the power and elegance of thermodynamics, one might recall Einstein’s often-quoted words:
“A theory is
the more impressive the greater the simplicity of its premises, the more
different kinds of things it relates, and the more extended its area of
applicability. Therefore the deep impression that classical
thermodynamics made upon me. It is the only physical theory of universal
content which I am convinced will never be overthrown, within the framework of
applicability of its basic concepts.”
From
a modern standpoint, Einstein’s admiration—though
justified for classical systems— overlooks an
inherent limitation. Here lies classical thermodynamics’
subtle paradox: its strength is its wide generality, yet that same generality narrow
its power. While it offers a small number of universal
principles applicable to diverse physical systems, it cannot
capture their richer complexities—thermal fluctuations, quantized energy
exchange, or nonequilibrium dynamics. However,
Feynman’s discussion serves as a valuable entry point into thermodynamics and
it prompts questions on how the classical theory must adapt to remain relevant
in contemporary physics.
1. Idealizations: The Foundations of Thermodynamics
“It is
the first part of the analysis of the properties of matter from the physical
point of view, in which, recognizing that matter is made out of a great many
atoms, or elementary parts, which interact electrically and obey the laws of
mechanics, we try to understand why various aggregates of atoms behave the way
they do (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-1).”
According to Feynman, analyzing
the properties of matter from a physical point of view requires at least three key idealizations.
They form the foundation of the kinetic theory of gases,
which bridges microscopic particle dynamics with macroscopic observables. The
key idealizations are:
1.
Atomic Model of Matter – Gas molecules are modeled as a large number of
randomly moving particles, enabling a statistical treatment of their behavior.
2.
Newton’s Laws of motion – They govern particle collisions
(momentum-conserving), e.g., linking microscopic motion to pressure, via
momentum transfer to container walls.
3.
Electrostatic Interactions – Intermolecular forces are assumed to be
predominantly Coulombic, while gravitational and magnetic effects are
negligible. In certain scenarios, Coulomb forces may be ignored, simplifying
the distribution of energy (or velocity).
These idealizations allow for a simplified but insightful framework, especially when applied to macroscopically homogeneous, isotropic, and uncharged systems (Callen, 1985).
“For
instance, when we compress something, it heats; if we heat it, it expands.
There is a relationship between these two facts which can be deduced
independently of the machinery underneath. This subject is called thermodynamics
(Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-2).”
Feynman’s
description
of thermodynamics emphasizes the interplay among heat and work, and the
physical properties of matter. More broadly, thermodynamics is the branch of
physics that explores how energy—particularly in the forms of heat and
work—relates to state variables such as temperature, pressure, and entropy,
thereby determining the behavior of physical systems. The term thermodynamics—derived
from the Greek therme (heat) and dynamis (power)—means “heat in
motion” or “heat power.” This name can be somewhat misleading: classical
thermodynamics primarily addresses equilibrium states, which are static or time-independent,
rather than dynamic processes (Atkins & de Paula, 2010). Despite its wide-ranging
applicability, thermodynamics is a phenomenological theory—its laws are grounded
in empirical observation, instead of derived from microscopic principles. Kinetic
theory, by contrast, provides a statistical foundation for thermodynamic
behavior and bridges the gap to statistical mechanics.
“We
shall also find that the subject can be attacked from a nonatomic point of
view, and that there are many interrelationships of the properties of
substances… The deepest understanding of thermodynamics comes, of course, from
understanding the actual machinery underneath, and that is what we shall do: we
shall take the atomic viewpoint from the beginning and use it to
understand the various properties of matter and the laws of thermodynamics
(Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-2).”
An
automotive analogy may help clarify the distinctions among thermodynamics,
kinetic theory, and statistical mechanics:
- Thermodynamics is like
reading a car’s speedometer—it offers a macroscopic description (nonatomic viewpoint) based on observable
quantities, without reference to microscopic mechanisms.
- Kinetic theory is akin to
analyzing the engine’s revolutions per minute (RPM) to explain the car’s
speed—it adopts a microscopic perspective (atomic viewpoint) to understand
macroscopic behavior in terms of particle motion.
- Statistical mechanics is
like the general theory of engines—it provides a unifying framework that
applies probabilistic principles to a wide range of systems, but not
limited to gases.
Note
that Feynman’s terms ‘nonatomic point of view’ and ‘atomic viewpoint’
correspond to what is commonly known as macroscopic and microscopic
perspectives respectively.
2. Approximations:
From Microscopic Chaos to Macroscopic Order
“Anyone
who wants to analyze the properties of matter in a real problem might want to
start by writing down the fundamental equations and then try to solve them
mathematically. Although there are people who try to use such an approach,
these people are the failures in this field; the real successes come to those
who start from a physical point of view, people who have a rough
idea where they are going and then begin by making the right kind of
approximations, knowing what is big and what is small in a given
complicated situation (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-2).”
Thermodynamics describes macroscopic properties—such as temperature and entropy—without invoking the microscopic details of matter. Statistical mechanics, in contrast, provides a deeper foundation by using probability theory and statistical methods to connect the microscopic behavior of particles to these observable thermodynamic quantities. Since tracking the motion of every individual particle is practically impossible, statistical approaches serve as a bridge between microscopic disorder (e.g., particle velocities and collisions) and macroscopic regularity (e.g., temperature and pressure). For example, the ideal gas law models gases as collections of non-interacting point particles, while the Van der Waals equation incorporates molecular size and intermolecular forces, offering a more realistic description of real gases. In this context, Feynman’s remark about “knowing what is big and what is small” can be interpreted not only in terms of physical size, but as an invitation to identify which variables significantly affect a system’s macroscopic behavior and which can be safely ignored.
“As an interesting example,
we all know that equal volumes of gases, at the same pressure and temperature,
contain the same number of molecules. The law of multiple proportions, that
when two gases combine in a chemical reaction the volumes needed always stand
in simple integral proportions, was understood ultimately by Avogadro to mean
that equal volumes have equal numbers of atoms. Now why do
they have equal numbers of atoms? (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-2).”
In 1808, Joseph Gay-Lussac
observed that gases react in simple whole-number volume ratios—e.g., 2 volumes
of hydrogen combine with 1 volume of oxygen to form 2 volumes of water vapor (2H₂
+ O₂ → 2H₂O). However, John Dalton (1808) rejected Gay-Lussac’s findings
because Dalton incorrectly assumed water had the formula HO. The turning point
came in 1811 when Amedeo Avogadro proposed two revolutionary ideas:
(1) equal gas volumes, under
the same temperature and pressure, contain equal number of molecules;
(2) Many gases, including
hydrogen and oxygen, exist as diatomic molecules.
Avogadro’s insight resolved the discrepancy in Dalton’s model by correctly identifying the composition of water and explaining why volume ratios align with molecular stoichiometry. Yet his ideas were largely ignored until 1860, when Stanislao Cannizzaro revived them at the Karlsruhe Congress, enabling chemists to determine atomic masses with consistency.
“Now why do
they have equal numbers of atoms? Can we deduce from Newton’s laws that the
number of atoms should be equal? (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-2).”
Newton’s laws of motion alone cannot explain Avogadro’s principle, because they deal with how every particle move—not with the big picture of how a large number of particles behave together. Avogadro’s insight depended on recognizing gases as composed of discrete molecules with definite stoichiometries—a chemical idea beyond the scope of Newton’s laws. While classical mechanics can explain how particle collisions generate pressure, but connecting equal volumes to equal numbers of molecules requires statistical averaging. (You need to average over a large number of particles to get meaningful results.) The ideal gas law (PV = nRT), which formalizes Avogadro’s principle*, emerges only when Newton’s laws are combined with molecular assumptions and statistical reasoning. Thus, Feynman’s question underscores this gap: classical physics alone cannot explain macroscopic gas behavior without invoking probability and the atomic nature of matter.
* Avogadro’s principle (n ∝ V at
fixed P, T) is embedded in the ideal gas law PV
= nRT and this requires assuming gases are composed of discrete
molecules (a non-Newtonian idea).
3. Limitations: Where Classical Thermodynamics Fails
“… from a physical standpoint, the actual behavior of the atoms is not
according to classical mechanics, but according to quantum mechanics,
and a correct understanding of the subject cannot be attained until we
understand quantum mechanics (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-1).”
Feynman
rightly remarks that classical mechanics is inadequate for understanding atomic
behavior, which fundamentally requires quantum mechanics. However, he could
have been more precise about the limitations of classical thermodynamics, particularly
its failure to accurately describe systems under certain conditions. While
classical thermodynamics is a widely applicable theory, it breaks down when
applied to quantum systems such as photons, ultracold atoms, or few-particle system.
For example, quantum systems exhibit non-classical behavior due to their
sensitivity to environmental interactions, which can induce decoherence and
destroy their coherent quantum states. Thus, quantum thermodynamics has emerged
as a suitable framework that redefines heat, work, and temperature in contexts
where fluctuations, discreteness, and quantum correlations are unavoidable. It
extends thermodynamic principles into the quantum domain, where basic assumptions
underpinning the classical theory no longer apply.
“Here, unlike the case of billiard balls and automobiles, the difference
between the classical mechanical laws and the quantum-mechanical laws is very
important and very significant, so that many things that we will deduce by
classical physics will be fundamentally incorrect. Therefore there will be
certain things to be partially unlearned; however, we shall indicate in every
case when a result is incorrect, so that we will know just where the ‘edges’
are (Feynman et al., 1963, p. 39-1).”
In his textbook Statistical Mechanics, Feynman writes: “If a system is very weakly coupled to a heat bath at a given 'temperature,' if the coupling is indefinite or not known precisely, if the coupling has been on for a long time, and if all the 'fast' things have happened and all the 'slow' things not, the system is said to be in thermal equilibrium.” This emphasizes that thermal equilibrium is not just about fast processes such as molecules settling into a Maxwell-Boltzmann distribution. It also requires that the system has interacted long enough with its environment to reach a stable state, while slower processes (e.g., container erosion) remain negligible. Thermodynamics holds under such conditions, but its accuracy depends on system size. In large systems (over 1,000 particles), fluctuations average out, making macroscopic quantities well-defined. In small systems (under 100 particles), fluctuations dominate, and corrections from statistical mechanics are needed. While thermodynamics may apply at the nanoscale, its assumptions must be used with care, as the boundary between large and small systems is inherently fuzzy.
Review
Questions:
1.
What idealizations underpin classical thermodynamics,
and how do they simplify reality?
2.
How does statistical mechanics employ
approximations, and what justifies them?
3.
When does classical thermodynamics fail, and how do modern frameworks address its
limitations?
The
moral of the Lesson (In Feynman’s spirit):
What
makes a theory great? Simple principles, surprising connections, and wide
applicability. Thermodynamics has all three—it’s the one theory
I’d bet my life on.
But
here’s the twist: a theory that powerful comes with its own limits.
Thermodynamics is like a brilliant, no-nonsense old professor—it delivers
rock-solid answers, but only to the big, timeless questions. Ask it about the
messy details, the fluctuations, the microscopic chaos, and it just shrugs and
says: "Not my department!"
References:
Avogadro,
A. (1811). Essay on a Manner of Determining the Relative Masses of the
Elementary Molecules of Bodies, and the Proportions in Which They Enter Into
These Compounds. Journal de Physique.
Callen,
H. B. (1985). Thermodynamics and an introduction to thermostatistics
(2nd ed.). Wiley.
Cannizzaro, S. (1860). Sunto di un Corso di
Filosofia Chimica. Paper presented at the Karlsruhe Congress.
Dalton,
J. (1808). A New System of Chemical Philosophy. Manchester: Bickerstaff.
Einstein,
A. (1970). Autobiographical notes. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), Albert
Einstein: Philosopher-scientist (pp. 1–95). Open Court. (Original work
published 1949).
Feynman,
R. P. (2018). Statistical mechanics: a set of lectures. CRC press.
Feynman,
R. P., Leighton, R. B., & Sands, M. (1963). The Feynman lectures on
physics, Vol. I: Mainly mechanics, radiation, and heat. Addison-Wesley.
Gay-Lussac, J. L. (1808). Mémoire sur la
combinaison des substances gazeuses entre elles. Annales
de Chimie.
No comments:
Post a Comment